Material implication

Status: notes; belief: possible

Contents

This document outlines some of the common explanations surrounding the material implication connective in propositional logic. The connective is most commondly represented using an arrow such as \(\to\) or \(\implies\) (even \(\supset\) in older texts), and when placed between two propositions as in “\(p \to q\)”, is supposed to mean “if \(p\), then \(q\)”. Moreover, this connective is defined as a truth function as follows.

In other words, \(p\to q\) is equivalent to writing \(\neg p \vee q\). A problem arises when working off this definition, however, because the conditions for truth given above do not correspond to the natural language sense of “if \(p\), then \(q\)”. The purpose of this document then is to explain why the material implication is defined as it is, and to aid in an intuitive understanding of the connective.

Two Naive Examples

Consider the conditional proposition “if one is in Berkeley, then one is in California”. We wish to know when this proposition is false and when it is true. To analyze this proposition, we consider various cases:

From the above analysis, we might conclude that the conditional proposition indeed is the same as the material conditional; the conditional proposition “if one is in Berkeley, then one is in California” was seen to be false only when the antecedent is true and the consequent is false, and true otherwise. As the title of this section implies, however, this analysis is naive in that it works in favor of human intuition, and conveniently hides problems with the approach. The next example shows how a similar example can work against human intuition.

Consider the conditional proposition “if one is in Berkeley, then one is in Massachusetts”. We present a similar analysis of this proposition:

From our preceding analysis, we obtain a new truth table for the conditional proposition:

\(p\) \(q\) \(p\rightarrow q\)
T T T
T F F
F T F
F F F

This seems strange, and indeed especially strange if we want to use the conditional proposition in a mathematical context—for this, as mentioned earlier, the proposition should only depend on properties of a formal system, presumably only the truth values of the constituent propositions, i.e., the truth values of \(p\) and \(q\). We presumably also want the conditional proposition to have a systematic method of evaluating the truth; one thing to note is that the material conditional already achieves this. To attempt to resolve this issue, we will now move on and consider various other analyses. We may conclude this section by saying that perhaps our examples were not well chosen; better examples could have been found within pure mathematics. This remark, however, simply cements the title for this section.

Tarski

The divergency between the usage of the phrase “if…, then…” in ordinary language and its usage in mathematical logic has been at the root of lengthy and even passionate discussions,—in which, by the way, professional logicians took only a minor part. (It is perhaps surprising, that considerably less attention was paid to the analogous divergency in the case of the word “or”.) It has been objected that logicians, on account of their adoption of the concept of material implication, arrived at paradoxes and even at plain nonsense. This has resulted in an outcry for a reform of logic, and in particular, for bringing about a far-reaching rapprochement between logic and ordinary language with regard to the use of implication.

It would be hard to grant that these criticisms are well founded. There is no phrase in ordinary language which has a precisely determined meaning. It would scarcely be possible to find two people who would use every word with exactly the same meaning, and even in the language of a single person the meaning of a given word may vary from one period of the person’s life to another. Moreover, the meaning of words of everyday language is usually very complicated; it depends not only on the external form of the word, but also on the circumstances in which it is uttered, and sometimes even on subjective psychological factors. If a scientist wants to transfer a concept from everyday life into a science and to establish general laws concerning this concept, he (or she) must always make its content clearer, more precise, and simpler, and free it from inessential attributes; it does not matter here whether he is a logician who is concerned with the phrase “if…, then…”, or, for instance, a physicist wanting to establish the exact meaning of the word “metal”. In whatever way the scientist realizes his task, the resulting usage of the term will deviate more or less from the practice of everyday language. If, however, he states explicitly in what sense he decides to use the term, and if afterwards he acts always in accordance with this decision, then nobody will be in a position to object, or to argue that his procedure leads to nonsensical results.

Ramsey

The following is taken from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy1 and written by Ramsey. Note that the notation for negation has been changed.

If two people are arguing ‘If \(p\), then \(q\)?’ and are both in doubt as to \(p\), they are adding \(p\) hypothetically to their stock of knowledge and arguing on that basis about \(q\); so that in a sense ‘If \(p\), \(q\)’ and ‘If \(p\), \(\neg q\)’ are contradictories. We can say that they are fixing their degree of belief in \(q\) given \(p\). If \(p\) turns out false, these degrees of belief are rendered void. If either party believes not \(p\) for certain, the question ceases to mean anything to him except as a question about what follows from certain laws or hypotheses.

The number analogy

[sec:The number analogy]

One can also construct the following analogy. Let T and F be \(1\) and \(0\) respectively; so to each proposition a number is assigned. Then define \(\neg p := |p-1|\); define \(p\wedge q := \min(p,q) = pq\); define \(p\vee q := \max(p,q) = p+q-pq\); define \[p\to q := \begin{cases} 1, &\text{ if }p\leq q; \\ 0, &\text{ if }p>q; \end{cases}\] and finally define \[p\leftrightarrow q := \begin{cases} 1, &\text{ if }p=q\\ 0, &\ \mathrm{if }\ p\ne q \end{cases}\]

Furthering the analogy

[sub:Furthering the analogy] The following is originally from a Google Buzz that Terence Tao posted2. The conditional proposition “if \(p\), then \(q\)” is the same as “\(p\) is at most as true as \(q\)” and “\(q\) is at least as true as \(p\)”. This can easily be seen using the number analogy and some logical equivalences. First note that \(p\to q = p\leftrightarrow (p\wedge q) = p\leftrightarrow\min(p,q)\) because for any \(p\) and \(q\), each produces the same digit. (Note in particular that each only produces a \(0\) when \(p=1\) and \(q=0\).) Consider what \(p\leftrightarrow\min(p,q)\) is stating. It says that \(p\) is the same as the lesser of \(p\) and \(q\); so even if \(p\) is large, it cannot exceed \(q\); i.e., \(p\) is at most \(q\).

Now note that \(p\to q = q \leftrightarrow \max(p,q)\). We see that \(q\leftrightarrow \max(p,q)\) says \(q\) is the same as the greater of \(p\) and \(q\); so even if \(q\) is small, it cannot be smaller than \(p\); i.e., \(q\) is at least \(p\).

In fact, something exactly like this happens in fuzzy logic.

Subset analogy

It’s possible to think of \(p\to q\) as \(P \subseteq Q\). Indeed, we need only define \(P = \{1 : p\}, Q = \{1 : q\}\), so that we have the correspondence:

\(p\) \(q\) \(p \to q\) \(P\) \(Q\) \(P \subseteq Q\)
T T T \(\{1\}\) \(\{1\}\) T
T F F \(\{1\}\) \(\emptyset\) F
F T T \(\emptyset\) \(\{1\}\) T
F F T \(\emptyset\) \(\emptyset\) T

In this sense, the vacuous implication \(\mathrm{F}\to q\) for any proposition \(q\) becomes the similarly vacuous \(\emptyset\subseteq Q\) for any set \(Q\); see Halmos’s explanation for the latter.

Halmos

As Halmos states in his Naive Set Theory (page 8),

The empty set is a subset of every set, or, in other words, \(\emptyset\subset A\) for every \(A\). To establish this, we might argue as follows. It is to be proved that every element in \(\emptyset\) belongs to \(A\); since there are no elements in \(\emptyset\), the condition is automatically fulfilled. The reasoning is correct but perhaps unsatisfying. Since it is a typical example of a frequent phenomenon, a condition holding in the “vacuous” sense, a word of advice to the inexperienced reader might be in order. To prove that something is true about the empty set, prove that it cannot be false. How, for instance, could it be false that \(\emptyset\subset A\)? It could be false only if \(\emptyset\) had an element that did not belong to \(A\). Since \(\emptyset\) has no elements at all, this is absurd. Conclusion: \(\emptyset\subset A\) is not false, and therefore \(\emptyset\subset A\) for every \(A\).


  1. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-conditionals/#RamTesConTheCon

  2. https://profiles.google.com/114134834346472219368/buzz/YNHWb5mzEKP


Tags: logic, math.

Creative Commons License
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.